Accéder au contenu principal

Articles

Modalities in Scientific Representation

Articles récents

Communal Norms of Representation are Conceptual

The thrust of the previous post is that there are two main levels of analysis when discussing representation in science: relevance and accuracy, or what a representation is about and what it says. Let us focus first on conditions of relevance. Consider any model M , and any object O . The question I want to ask is: in what sense might we say that it is possible that M represents O , or that it must be so (independently of whether it represents it well )? We should first dispell an ambiguity in this question. Are we talking in general, or in a particular context? I have argued in my past research ( Ruyant 2021 ) that there is an important difference between two senses of “represent”: either it refers to norms at play in the epistemic community (such as: the Lotka-Volterra model represents a prey-predator system), or it refers to a specific use in context (the model of the pendulum that I’m using represents the oscillation of my clock). However, the first sense is generally more

Epistemic Representation: The Basics

Now that we have reached a rough taxonomy of modalities, let us talk about representation. I think it will be enough to have this rough picture in mind, which, I reckon, should be uncontroversial aspects of representation: Inferentialism: An epistemic representation (such as a scientific model, a map, a realistic drawing) can be used to make inferences about target systems of a relevant kind in concrete situations. Misrepresentation: It is possible, for a representation, to represent its target inaccurately. I take inferentialism to be a minimalist theory of representation. This does not tell against theories that attempt to give more substance to representation, but only defines a common ground. As for the possibility of misrepresentation, it has been challenged notably on the ground that representation would be a “success term” or a thick term ( Poznic 2018 ; Chakravartty 2010, pp. 209–10 ), but I’m utterly unconvinced that this is the case. “Cruel” is a thick term, and

Bonus: A Puzzle about Conceptual Changes

Let us say a bit more about a puzzle that came about in previous posts. Let p be "the sum of the angles of a triangle is lower than 180 degrees" and C a modal operator "it is conceivable that". Consider the situation before anyone even conceived of non-euclidean geometries as a consistent alternative to euclidean geometry. Then, intuitively speaking, p was not conceivable (¬Cp). But we now know that p is true of some triangles, because the geometry of the universe is non-euclidean (p). On the other hand, it is quite natural to think that conceptual modality is factive, that is, that if something stems from conceptual necessity, then it is also true (¬C¬p→p), and this implies the converse, that if something is true, then it is conceivable (p→Cp). But these three premises are mutually inconsistent, hence our trilemma: one of the following statements must be false. ¬Cp p p→Cp So, we have exactly three options: (A) either we can claim that p always was conceivab

Factivity and Deontic Modals

We have explored so far, in the previous posts, the differences between conceptual, epistemic, metaphysical and natural modalities, arguing that the two first have representational targets, but differ by the mind-dependence of their source, and that the two last have worldly targets. An important common characteristic of all these modalities is factivity: if P is necessary, in any sense of the term, then P is the case. The converse of this theorem of alethic modal logic is that if P is the case, then P is also possible, that is, compatible with the source of necessity. This is notably not the case of deontic and practical modalities: maybe it must be the case that no one walks on the grass according to the norms, but someone is doing it right now, or maybe we must stop the water from flowing into our basement, but we are not actually doing it. Deontic laws, contrarily to natural ones, can be broken. Another way of making the difference is in terms of direction of fit. If someone w

Beyond the Objective/Subjective Distinction

As we have seen in the previous post, we can make sense of the division between subjective and objective modalities in terms of whether they concern worldly objects, or rather our attitudes towards them. The target of necessary constraints (whether they are worldly or representational) matters, not the source of necessity. But what about the finer distinctions: what distinguishes between epistemic and conceptual possibility? And what distinguishes metaphysical and natural necessity? Consider epistemic and conceptual possibilities first. An hypothesis that flows naturally from our previous remarks is that the target of necessity is representational in both cases, but the source of necessity is markedly different in each case. With conceptual and logical necessity, the source of necessity, the origin of the constraint, lies in our representational capacities, in us, while with epistemic necessity, it lies in the external world. This means reintroducing an analytic/synthetic distinctio

Objective and subjective modalities

Remember our list of kinds of modalities from the previous post: Logico-conceptual (Bachelor cannot be married) Epistemic (she might be at home) Metaphysical (water molecules are of the H2O kind) Natural (heavy objects must fall) Deontic (she must work tonight) Practical (we could use wood to build this plane) The two first modalities above, epistemic and logico-conceptual, are often thought to be mind-dependent or subjective, while the two next ones, metaphysical and natural, are mind-independent or objective (as for the two last ones, let us put them aside for now). Objective modalities are often used in order to analyse explanations or causation. These are the ones typically involved in counterfactual talk (if you had got up earlier, you woudn't have missed your train), although sometimes conceptual necessities are thus expressed as well (if he were a bachelor, he wouldn't be married). The distinction between objective and subjective modalities could be understood as

The Variety of Modalities

Modals are expressed by words such as "must", "have to", "ought to", "may", "can", "could", "should", "necessarily", "possibly". As a general rule, something is said to be possible if it is not necessary that it is not the case, and conversely, something is necessary if it is not possible that it is not the case, but beyond this, there is a variety of use. Here are a few distinctions between various kinds of possibilities. I will discuss in the next articles some criteria for disinguishing them, and attempt to reach a taxonomy. A logical or conceptual possibility anything that is not self-contradictory, that makes sense, that one can express or conceive without reaching a logical contradiction (for example respecting the fact that for any proposition, it must be that either p or not p"). Example: it is conceivable that aliens exist. An epistemic possibility anything that is com