Accéder au contenu principal

The Variety of Modalities

Haeckel arbol bn

Modals are expressed by words such as "must", "have to", "ought to", "may", "can", "could", "should", "necessarily", "possibly". As a general rule, something is said to be possible if it is not necessary that it is not the case, and conversely, something is necessary if it is not possible that it is not the case, but beyond this, there is a variety of use. Here are a few distinctions between various kinds of possibilities. I will discuss in the next articles some criteria for disinguishing them, and attempt to reach a taxonomy.

A logical or conceptual possibility

anything that is not self-contradictory, that makes sense, that one can express or conceive without reaching a logical contradiction (for example respecting the fact that for any proposition, it must be that either p or not p"). Example: it is conceivable that aliens exist.

An epistemic possibility

anything that is compatible with what we know or with available evidence and what follows from it (such as "she must be at home"). Example: she might be sleeping.

A metaphysical possibility

anything that is compatible with the nature or identity or essence of things (that molecules of water are of the kind H2O). Example: the fundamental constants of the universe could have been different.

A natural possibility

anything that is compatible with the laws of nature (such as the law that heavy objects must fall towards the ground). This is the modality typically used in scientific explanations, or to analyse causation. Example: the ball could have broken the window.

A deontic possibility

anything that is compatible with norms (such as "she has to stay at work tonight"). Example: she is allowed to make a call.

A practical possibility

anything that is compatible with our aims and capacities (such as "we must use light materials to fly"). Example: we could use wood to build this plane.

Note that in all these cases necessity naturally comes first, in the sense that it is easier to define possibility in terms of compatibility with a source of necessity rather than to define necessity in terms of, say, what a set of a priori unrelated possibilities have in common. A given statement can be compatible with many sources of necessity, so it's not always clear in what sense we mean that something is possible, but when saying that something must be so, it is generally easier to see in virtue of what (although there is leeway in fixing the relevant background conditions in counterfactual talk, which is often a source of disagreement, this can generally be made explicit). One could argue, as Divers (2004) did some times ago, that as a matter of generality, a commitment to a mere possibility is not binding, while a commitment to a necessity does affect our inferences and actions (an exception, perhaps, is a practical possibility that would motivate us to act). For these reasons, this work will be primarily focused on understanding necessity

We could suspect that this order of primacy is reversed when it comes to modal epistemology, in the sense that we are directly acquainted with actualised possibilities, not necessities (see my Modal Empiricism). However, we are not concerned with modal epistemology here, but with having a conceptual grasp of what different kinds of modalities are, so our primary interest lies in sources of necessity. I will also put aside general scepticism about whether there really are constraints of necessity of the kind considered, because again, my aim is merely conceptual.

I will examine in the next posts some criteria for distinguishing various kinds of necessity conceptually: what exactly makes then different? My aim is to reach some kind of taxonomy, before examining its relation to modeling activities.

Commentaires

Posts les plus consultés de ce blog

Modalities in Scientific Representation

The aim of this blog is to present the result of my Marie Skłodowska-Curie research project "Modalities in Scientific Representation", realised in Madrid between September 2021 and December 2023 (which was in direct continutation with my project realised at UNAM between 2019-2023). A large spectrum of discourse in science is typically analysed in modal terms, that is, in terms of what is possible or necessary. This includes scientific explanations, physical laws and constraints, causation, counterfactual reasoning and probabilities. There is a large amount of literature on the metaphysics of natural necessity in science at a general level, with proposed analyses in terms of governing laws of nature, or dispositions, etc. However, necessity comes in many varieties and other kinds of modalities than natural necessity are involved in scientific discourse. This is certainly the case for epistemic modality, involved, for example, in assessing the credibility of a hypothesis, bu...

Bonus: A Puzzle about Conceptual Changes

Let us say a bit more about a puzzle that came about in previous posts. Let p be "the sum of the angles of a triangle is lower than 180 degrees" and C a modal operator "it is conceivable that". Consider the situation before anyone even conceived of non-euclidean geometries as a consistent alternative to euclidean geometry. Then, intuitively speaking, p was not conceivable (¬Cp). But we now know that p is true of some triangles, because the geometry of the universe is non-euclidean (p). On the other hand, it is quite natural to think that conceptual modality is factive, that is, that if something stems from conceptual necessity, then it is also true (¬C¬p→p), and this implies the converse, that if something is true, then it is conceivable (p→Cp). But these three premises are mutually inconsistent, hence our trilemma: one of the following statements must be false. ¬Cp p p→Cp So, we have exactly three options: (A) either we can claim that p always was...

Epistemic Representation: The Basics

Now that we have reached a rough taxonomy of modalities, let us talk about representation. I think it will be enough to have this rough picture in mind, which, I reckon, should be uncontroversial aspects of representation: Inferentialism: An epistemic representation (such as a scientific model, a map, a realistic drawing) can be used to make inferences about target systems of a relevant kind in concrete situations. Misrepresentation: It is possible, for a representation, to represent its target inaccurately. I take inferentialism to be a minimalist theory of representation. This does not tell against theories that attempt to give more substance to representation, but only defines a common ground. As for the possibility of misrepresentation, it has been challenged notably on the ground that representation would be a “success term” or a thick term ( Poznic 2018 ; Chakravartty 2010, pp. 209–10 ), but I’m utterly unconvinced that this is the case. “Cruel” is a thick term, and...